How do you write about a book that is almost 600 pages long
(in small print), has 25 pages of references, and the ambition to explain political
institutions from the dawn of mankind to the French Revolution, from
kinship-based bands of hunters to Voltaire? This was Francis Fukuyama’s
objective in this monumental (yet eminently readable) book, “The Origins of PoliticalOrder” (note the plural).
My review, given the size and importance of the book, will be
done in two parts, First, here, I will review the logic of the arguments put
forward by Fukuyama. In the second review, I will engage into some critique.
There is one key idea of the book. If you wish to have a functional
political order that enables economic growth and gives people freedom from arbitrariness
of the sovereign or from oppression by their peers, you need three components:
(i) a strong state, (ii) rule of law, and (iii) accountability.
It may seem at first that this is nothing especially new, but
the way that Fukuyama presents his case is. A strong state is needed to provide
public goods (most important being domestic law and order, protection of
property, and defense against external attack). But the strong state has to be “penned in” from two sides. From the
top (as it were) by an ideology or religion that imposes limits on the state:
this is the rule of law. Sovereign himself, however powerful, has to be subject
to law. The second constraint comes from below: the state needs to be accepted,
that is, accountable to people (where “people” is variously defined). We thus achieve
the seemingly impossible: we have a strong state that cannot behave as it pleases,
and needs some form of consent of those it governs.
The three independent component parts allow Fukuyama to show
how one of them was achieved by some societies, two by others, but that they came
together, all three, only in the 17th century England. China is the
case of what Fukuyama calls “precocious state formation”. Qin China was the
first to create a state: a process which, according to Fukuyama, is fundamentally
unnatural because to have a state means to fight “patrimonialism”, people’s innate
tendency to favor their own kin and tribe. State on the contrary requires clear, impersonal rules and system of advancement based on some general criteria including
merit. Qin China, through ruthless centralization, and the defeat of a number
of regional aristocracies, achieved that. But, it achieved it, Fukuyama thinks,
too early. China thus created a powerful state –a thing which eludes many
communities still today, more than two millennia after the Chinese did it—but it
never created rule of law nor accountability. It was absolutist, from the start
until today.
The absence of the rule of law of course does not mean that there is
no law. What is today called “rule by law” (as opposed to the rule of law) is what Legalism was in China: ability of the Emperor to create laws at will, and
have them obeyed. There was no lawlessness nor anomie but there was neither
rule of law that constrained the state: a set of rules that can be changed only
through previously agreed procedures.
There were cases of states that had an early form of the rule
of law: religious rules that limited sovereign’s ability to do whatever he
wanted. But such societies lacked either accountability, or both accountability
and a strong state. Religions, according to Fukuyama, were useful in producing the
rule of law because they placed the sovereign under one higher law: divine.
This was the case in Islam (Umayyads, Abbasids and later Ottomans and Memluks),
India thanks to Hinduism and Buddhism, and Europe thanks to Christianity (or rather mostly
thanks to Catholicism).
The absence of rule of law in China is seen as due to the
absence of a codified religion with its divinely-ordained rules. In effect, codification
of religion—being a “people of the book”—is
what Fukuyama believes is needed for the creation of early rule of law. Writing
down divine rules, and having them “embodied” in a group of scholars or religious
orders (ulamas, Brahmins, Christian clergy) whose main purpose is to watch
over their application, limited the arbitrary power of the sultans, Indian princes
and European kings.
Ottomans come for a special praise because they were able to
create a strong state and an early rule of law (the latter, as just explained,
thanks to Islam). The strong state was built on the backs of devşirme, the practice of abducting Christian
children from their parents in order to create an elite corps of soldier- and administrator-slaves.
This (in many ways abhorrent) practice allowed Ottomans to create a
non-patrimonial state, to keep the grandees at bay, and not let kinship and family
relations dominate the state. Ottoman decay began when janissaries were finally
able to parlay their advantage to their children and then, together with magnates,
to repatrimonialize the state. A one-generation aristocracy is the best way to
ensure a strong non-patrimonial state. But it is hard to achieve because of people’s desire to transmit
their advantages to offspring.
Accountability is the last to get on the scene. Until the
European democratic revolutions, accountability was mostly non-existent (the Sultans
did not have to ask people for permission for their actions) and was, at best,
limited. It worked through the power of aristocracy, clergy or gentry to provide
checks on the sovereign, principally to control the introduction of new taxes
(Cortes in Spain, regional parlements
in France, zemskiy sobor in Russia).
But until the advent of the English parliament accountability was not only limited
to a few classes, but sporadically exercised and even more sporadically obeyed. It thus waxed and waned depending on the relative
powers of the sovereign and aristocracy.
When does the political order decay? When the state is incapable
to reform itself to respond to new
challenges (say, a powerful neighbor) and when it gets repatrimonalized. The decay section is not exactly novel (to be unable to reform is not very original),
but the emphasis on repatrimonization as the source of decay allows us to
better see that the state remains an unnatural organization in the sense that
it is permanently in danger of succumbing to the more atavistic instincts of
human nature—to prefer own kin rather than be subject to impersonal rules.
To have a strong state is therefore to be engaged in a permanent
struggle against family. Christianity, according to Fukuyama, was particularly good
in fighting family ties; Chinese history can be summarized as one endless conflict
between the state and family. Every time you give a job to your friend or cousin,
you are repartrimonalizing the state. And think how unnatural it is to behave
equally toward everybody for it means, as noted by Montesquieu, that “a virtuous
man has no friends”.
In the next post, I will provide some thoughts on the organization
of the book, and a few critiques.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.