The seminal work
in political philosophy for the era of globalization is John Rawls’ “The law of
peoples” (LoP). It was written in 1999. I was attracted to it in the early
2000s as I was then already working on global inequality which was a totally new
topic, entirely ignored, in economics. The only thing that came remotely close
to it in economics was the Heckschler-Ohlin-Samuelson trade theorem whereby wage
inequality should go down in poor countries and up in rich countries when they
engage in trade. But this was such a small part of globalizations: it dealt
with wages only and left out other types of income; it left out capital flows,
development aid, migration, outsourcing. None of that was discussed in
economics (and mostly still is not) in a global framework as opposed to 2-country
2-goods very limiting framework. But political philosophers have thought more about it.
In the late
1990s, John Rawls turned his attention from how a single nation-state should be
organized (as in his Theory of Justice, ToJ) to how the world should be organized.
Obviously, it had to be done at a very abstract level and, as will be seen,
that abstract level comes very close to the situation Rawls (and the world) seemed
to face in the 1990s. But, and it will be my key point here, that situation has
dramatically changed in the past 20 years so that the abstract sketch of the world
made by Rawls is no longer compatible
with what we see today and thus the recommendations Rawls drew from that sketch
are irrelevant.
In LoP,
Rawls abandoned the metaphor of individuals meeting behind the veil of ignorance
to agree on an a priori basis on the principles of justice in their societies. That
rule still holds, according to Rawls, in individual societies but not in the
world of nation-states whose representatives (but not individuals themselves)
meet to agree on the principles that would guide their (inter-societal) relations.
Rawls has five types of societies:
liberal (these are the same societies with which his ToJ is concerned), consultative
hierarchical societies, “burdened” societies, outlaw states (notice: not
societies) and benevolent absolutisms. We can drop the last because they never
play a role in LoP (I never understood why; perhaps Rawls just did not know what
to do with them). Both liberal and consultative hierarchical societies are
well-ordered societies (meaning that within each of them the principle upon which
they are based are reinforced by peoples’ daily actions); they respect each
other and the (different) principles upon which each is based. Burdened
societies cannot become liberal because they are held back by their poverty.
Outlaw states just go to war (for basically no reason; they just, like in a Hollywood
movie, seem to like being troublemakers).
So the rules
then become relatively simple—and some would even say simplistic. The
well-ordered societies, though different in their internal structure, can
coexist at peace because they respect each other, and liberal societies do not try
to impose their norms on consultative hierarchies. They do not try to export democracy.
Second, liberal societies have a duty to help the burdened societies but only as
far as they require to become liberal, which, in Rawls’ view, takes place at a
very low average level of income. After that point, even huge differences in
incomes within the group of well-ordered societies are no ground for continuation
of international aid. In other words, there is no reason for Norway to help Bangladesh
because they are both well-ordered.
Finally, Rawls is against migration as a
right or against migration as a way to alleviate global poverty and inequality.
Countries (that is, organized peoples) have control of their territory and they
alone decide whom they want to accept. They can accept refuges that flee persecution
but not economic migrants (which is by the way consistent with Rawls’ general underplaying
of the importance of income for our happiness).
So, this is
the sketch: liberal societies reaffirm their liberal principles daily, they
live in peace with hierarchical societies, the do not export democracy, they help
only the poorest countries and this very moderately, and they do not allow
economic migration.
As you can see, this is why I was attracted to Rawls:
unlike economists he does present a coherent sketch of the world and economic
rules.
So why do I
have a problem with Rawls’ taxonomy now?
Let me list
several changes that have happened during the past two decades and for which I just
do not find a place in Rawls’ taxonomy.
Liberal
democracies do not affirm the principles of liberalism, as Rawls expected, neither
domestically nor internationally. It was inconceivable for Rawls, when these societies are working well, that they would, as in the US now, generate a third or more
of “malcontent” population that clearly does not believe in liberal principles nor
is willing to affirm them in their daily lives. Far from it. This, plus the
pervasive role of money in electoral politics, lower tax rates for capital than
labor, neglect of public education etc. imply that domestically so called
liberal societies are very far from Rawls’ idea of liberalism. The difference
is so great that we cannot, I think, speak of the discrepancy any longer as the
expected difference between an abstract idea and what exist in reality. These societies
belong to an entirely different category.
Moreover, in
foreign policy, as became clear with the Iraq war, they act like outlaw states
since they break the fundamental rules on which the international community is
founded, namely absence of wars of aggression.
Thus, “liberal”
societies are both non-liberal (in the Rawlsian sense) domestically and act as outlaw
states.
The benign consultative
hierarchies that Rawls had in mind probably in order to fit Islamic societies in
his scheme are practically non-existent.
The Middle East is either in total chaos or in the grip of absolutist dictatorships
like Egypt, Saudi Arabia and the Gulf sheikdoms. Thus they are not well-ordered societies in Rawls’
terms.
There is no
place in his taxonomy for the multi-county non-state organizations like ISIS. A
general theory that has no place for organizations that do not accept current
state borders is clearly incomplete. (This is an issue on which Rawls is especially
weak because he takes borders as given, which is, as he wrote in the wake of the
break-up of the USSR, Czechoslovakia, Ethiopia and Yugoslavia, rather odd).
There is
also no place for what is now called illiberal democracy, namely a society that
has most of the accoutrements of a liberal society (elections, political
parties, NGOs), and yet where only one party or one leader ever wins elections and
where the media and the judiciary are directly or indirectly controlled.
Migrations, driven
by economic reasons and thus by global inequality, do not have a place in
Rawls. But they do exist in real life where economic migrants from Africa and
Asia into Europe or Mexico and Central America into the United States number millions.
But the theory that says that this should not happen is of no use when these
things do happen.
Finally, Rawls
grossly underrated the importance that people attach to income and wealth for
their happiness. Importance of pecuniary incentives has only increased with
globalization since income differences have become more visible.
The changes over
the past two decades have been, I believe, so remarkable that the typology
offered by Rawls has lost its relevance. But if the typology does not fit
reality then the recommended relations between the different societies, based
on this typology, do not have any relevance. This is why I think it is time to either
ditch Rawls or revise him very thoroughly. A job for political philosophers.