It is an immensely ambitious book. In
less than 300 pages, Paul Mason not only explains the past 300 years of capitalism
and the efforts to replace it with another system (socialism), but shows how it
would be eventually transformed and proposes a set of policies to help that transformation
along. Moreover, it is not a superficial book as it might seem at first by contrasting
the enormity of the material covered and the relatively slender size of the
volume. One should not be misled either by the folksy style used by Mason. The style may be journalistic, but the questions
asked, the quality of the discussion, and the objectives of the book are
first-rate.
The book can be read in many ways.
One could focus on the last three chapters which are of a programmatic nature
and intended to supply some positive objectives to the new left. Or one could discuss
the book’s belief in cyclical development of capitalism driven by the long-run Kondratieff’s
cycles (we are currently, according to Mason’s reading, in the upswing of the
fifth cycle). Or one could focus on Mason’s very brief but powerful history of
the workers’ movements (Chapter 7) and one of his rare agreements with Lenin
that workers could at best reach “trade-union consciousness” and were not interested
in overthrowing capitalism. Or one could debate the usefulness of Mason’s resuscitation
of Marx’s labor theory of value.
I will not do any of this since this
review is relatively short. I will discuss Mason’s view of the current state of
capitalism and of the objective forces that, he argues, lead it to postcapitalism.
The gist of Mason’s argument is that the ICT revolution is characterized by enormous
economies of scale which make the marginal cost of production of knowledge goods
close to zero, with both the quantities of capital and labor embodied in such products
tending to zero. Imagine an electronic blueprint of whatever needed for 3D
printing or a software directing the work of machines: once such investments
have been made there is hardly any need for additional live labor, and since the
capital (software) has a quasi infinite life, the share of capital “embodied”
in each unit of output is minimal (“what you ideally want is a machine that
never wears out, or the one that costs nothing to replace”, p. 166).
When the marginal cost of production goes
to zero, the price system no longer functions, nor can standard capitalism
exist: if profits are zero, we do not have a capitalist class, nor surplus value,
nor positive marginal product of capital, nor wage labor. We are approaching the world of mass abundance
where the usual rules of capitalism no longer apply. It is a bit like the world
of absolute zero temperature, or the world where time and energy become one. It
is in other words a world very far from the one that we inhabit now but it is where,
according to Mason, we are going.
What are the ways capitalists can
offset driving themselves out of existence? There are three ways, and to those
who have read Marxist literature of the early 1910s, they would be familiar because
similar issues were discussed then. The first is to create monopolies. This is
exactly what Apple, Amazon, Google and Microsoft are doing now. The economy can
become monopolized and cartelized as it did in the last decades of the 19th
and the first decades of the 20th century.
The second response is to reinforce
protection of intellectual property. This is again what the just mentioned
companies, or song producers and Disney are trying to do ever more aggressively
using the power of the state. (The reader would realize that protection of
property rights increases capital unit costs and thus prevents the marginal
cost of production dropping to zero.)
The third response is to continually
expand capitalism’s “field of action”: if profits in one area threaten to drop
to zero move to another area, “skating [forever] to the edge of chaos” between
expanding supply and falling prices, or …find new things that can be commercialized
and commodified.
Readers of Rosa Luxemburg would
recognize here a very similar idea, namely that the existence of capitalism depends
on its continued interaction with non-capitalist modes of production and once these
are exhausted capitalism will be driven to the world of zero profits. These
concerns have an even older pedigree, going back to Ricardo’s view that,
without the repeal of the Corn Laws, all capitalists’ profits will be eaten up
by landlords’ rents and development stifled, and to Marx’s “law of tendencial fall of the rate of profit” caused
by ever greater capital intensity of production.
So Mason’s points in this respect are
not new, but situating them at the current stage of capitalism and ITC revolution
is new. The three ways that capitalists try to redress the ineluctable decrease
of the rate of profit are all found wanting. If monopolies were a way to maintain
capitalism that would imply the end of technological progress. Capitalism would
become a “regressive” system. Not many people would disagree with Mason’s call
to suppress the monopolies such as Amazon and Microsoft. The same is true for
protection of property rights whose enforcement moreover is getting more and
more difficult.
So with a tendency of profits to go to
zero and inability to protect property rights, the only solution that remains is
commercialization of daily life (the new “field of action”). This is how Mason explains
the tendency of capitalists to move unto previously non-market transactions: to
create new goods out of our homes which we now rent by the day, out of our cars,
out of our free time. Practically every human interaction will have to be commodified:
mothers will charge each other a penny when they push each other’s kids on a swing
in the playground. But this, Mason argues,
can’t continue. There is a natural limit to what the humans will accept in terms
of commodification of daily activities: “you would have to treat people kissing
each other for free the way they treated poachers in the 19th century”
(p. 175).
Mason’s arguments are, I think, very persuasive
so far, but this is the place where I am tempted to part ways. His explanation of
why we are living through a period of unprecedented commodification of our
personal lives is very well taken, but his optimistic outlook that such
commodification faces limits as well as his emphasis on the increasing
importance of non-market transactions (open source software, writing blogs like
this one for free etc.) is wrong.
Let me start with the latter. Mason exaggerates
the importance of new technologies or new goods that are developed through cooperation
and supplied for free. Yes, many things can be accessed for nothing but even if
they seem to be provided voluntarily there is, in the background, a mercenary element:
you may write a code or text for free but this is done to influence others, become
noticed and ultimately paid for it. Mason
probably wrote his book for free; but the success of the book will ensure that
he would be paid for whatever next he says or writes. So focusing on the former
without including the latter is misleading.
Why is his view on commodification wrong?
Commodification is not just imposed on us externally through companies that
want to find new sources of profits. We are willingly participating in commodification
because through long socialization in capitalism, its global reach and thus
mimicry among those who have not been socialized as long, people have become capitalistic
calculating machines. We have each become a small center of capitalist thinking,
assigning implicit (”shadow”) prices to our time, our emotions or family relations.
The ultimate success of capitalism is
to have transformed, or developed, human nature into making each of us into excellent calculators of “pain
and pleasure”, “gain or loss” so much so that even if capitalist factory
production were to disappear today we would be selling each other services for
money: we shall become companies. Imagine an economy (similar externally to a very
primitive one) where all production is conducted at home. This would seem a
perfect model of a non-market economy. But if we had such an economy today, it
would be fully capitalistic because we would be selling all these goods and services
to each other: a neighbor will not keep an eye on your children for free; nobody
will share food with you but will charge you; you will make your husband pay
for sex and so forth. This is the world we are moving towards, and the field of
capitalistic operations is thus likely to become unlimited because it would
include each of us. “The factory in the cognitive capitalism is the whole of society”
(p. 139).
Capitalism will run for a very long time because
it was successful in transforming humans
into calculating machines endowed with limitless needs. What David Landes saw as one of the main contributions of
capitalism, better use of time and ability to express everything in terms of
abstract purchasing power, has moved now into our private lives. We do not need
capitalist mode of production in factories if we have all become capitalistic centers
ourselves.