A few days ago I wrote a post on wealth comparisons overtime. I have done such a comparison myself in “The haves and the have-nots” and
have used Adam Smith’s argument that person’s wealth ought to be measured in
the amount of labor he commands. In other words, wealth needs to be measured in
its historical context. I gave two examples of misleading wealth comparisons: over
time, when we try to use the same bundle of commodities to compare Croesus and Bezos,
and when we conflate wealth and power.
Here I would like to explain a bit more the problems with
historical comparisons of wealth (or income) because they have direct bearing
on our understanding of the past, and raise also some essentially philosophical
points.
The difficulty of measurement of wealth between different periods
derives not only because of our lack of data for most of the past but from the
inability to meaningfully compare wealth or consumption patterns in the past
with those of today. Some economists believe that if people in the past did not
have certain amenities that we have today they must have been infinitely poorer.
This is what one finds in Nordhaus
and DeLong’s view of historical progress as unfolfding through reduced cost of
artificial lighting, the approach that Angus Maddison (in “Contours of the World Economy: 1-2030”) termed
a “hallucigenic history”.
The logic of such authors is as follows. Take the example of artificial
lighting or voice recording. For Julius Caesar to read a book overnight, easily
move at night around his palace, or listen to the songs he liked would have required
perhaps hundreds of workers (slaves) to hold the torches or sing his favorite
arias all night. Even Caesar, if he were to do that night after night, might, after
some time, have run out of resources (or might have provoked a rebellion among
the singers). But for us the expense for a similar pleasure is very small, even
trivial, say $2 per night. Consequently, some people come to the conclusion
that Caesar must have had tiny wealth measured in today’s bundle of goods since
a repeated small nightly expense of $2 (in today’s prices) would have eventually
ruined him. Other people at Caesar’s time had obviously much less: ergo, the world
today is incomparably richer than before, and people then must have felt
horribly poor and deprived of all pleasurable things. (Even if you cannot feel
deprived of the things you do not know exist.)
The logic seems at first reasonable even if somewhat extreme.
But it is not reasonable. Let’s extend this logic, now in a different direction,
from us today to the next 500 years. Suppose that in 500 years people are able
to choose for their vacation between Mars, Venus, Pluto or perhaps even to go
further than that. Suppose they can fly around our solar system, go to the
bottom of the ocean, zip from one end of the Earth to another in a few minutes,
or do lots of fun things that we cannot imagine today, no more than Caesar
could have imagined that his singers’ voices could be recorded on a tiny chip and
reproduced ad infinitum at almost no cost. And when we then look at Jeff Bezos’
wealth today using the consumption opportunities of the future, that wealth is
likely to look to us –from the vantage point of 500 years hence- insignificant.
Bezos might be rich in our own terms, but he cannot fly to Mars this weekend,
no matter how much he tries.
So should we then absurdly turn around and claim that Jeff Bezos,
Bill Gates et al. are poor? Clearly not. But thus, equally clearly, rich Romans
were not poor either. In other words, we cannot compare wealth of vastly
different epochs by using one yardstick, whether it be the yardstick of the
past (which is on balance more reasonable) or the yardstick of the present. This
is a well-known problem for empirical economic historians. If time-periods are
not vastly apart, or rather if technologies and consumption baskets are not
vastly different, we can perhaps use some equal weighting of the baskets (½ of
the past and ½ of the present). But that clearly will not do for the very remote
periods.
This is why wealth has to be measured with a yardstick belonging
to the same time when that wealth exists.* And this is why Adam Smith’s approach
seems the only one that makes sense. No other commodity but labor power (an
hour of unskilled work) is both as unchanged over time in terms of effort exerted,
and yet paid the equivalent of different amounts of real goods and services
reflecting the general level of productivity of a society. It is both covariant
with wealth and an unvarying numeraire.
Angus Maddison who created the original series comparing
incomes of countries over a very long-run was perfectly aware of the problem.
He directed his scorn towards those who believed that looking at the past
through our today’s lenses made them treat everybody who lived then as “cavemen”:
“[Such authors as] Nordhaus and DeLong have constructed fairytale scenarios that
greatly exaggerate progress since 1800, before which they seem to believe that people
lived like cavemen. These views are fundamentally wrong.”
* The same problem
technically applies to cross-country comparisons at a given point in time. However
with globalization which brings similarity in technologies and consumption patterns
across the world the comparisons are much more meaningful.