When I taught
recently at the Summer School at Groningen University, I began my lecture on the
measurement of inequality by distinguishing between the Italian and English schools
as they were defined in 1921 by Corrado Gini:
“The methods
of Italian writers…are not…comparable to his [Dalton’s] own, inasmuch as their
purpose is to estimate, not the inequality of economic welfare, but the
inequality of incomes and wealth, independently of all hypotheses as to the
functional relations between these quantities and economic welfare or as to the
additive character of the economic welfare of individuals”. (Corrado Gini,
Measurement of Inequality of Incomes, Economic Journal, March 1921.)
I put myself
squarely in the camp of the “Italians”. Measurement of income inequality is
like measurement of any natural or social phenomenon. We measure inequality as
we measure temperature or height of people. The English (or welfarist) school believes
that the measure of income inequality is only a proxy for a measure of a more
fundamental phenomenon: inequality in welfare. The ultimate variable, according
to them, that we want to estimate is welfare
(or even happiness) and how it is distributed. Income provides only an empirically
feasible short-cut to it.
I would have
been sympathetic to that approach if I knew how individual utility can be measured.
There is, I believe, no way to compare utilities of different persons. We all
agree that the marginal utility must be diminishing in income because it is the
foundation of economic micro theory. (If
marginal utility of income were not decreasing, we would not be able to explain
why demand curves are sloping downward.) But we have no idea whether, whole
both your and my marginal utility functions are decreasing, my level of utility
may, at any point, be orders of magnitude greater than yours or the reverse.
The only way
for the “welfaristas” to solve this conundrum is to assume that all individuals
have the same utility function. This is such
an unrealistically bold assumption that I think nobody would really care to defend
it except as here where it is considered as a lesser evil that allows “welfaristas”
to cling to their Utilitarianism, to define measures like the Atkinson index
and to continue believing that the real thing we want and (they clam) do measure
is inequality in individual welfares.
Now, the welfarst approach continues to be associated with pro-equality policies.
Why?
Because if all people have the same utility function, then the optimal distribution
of income is such that everybody has the same income. If from that equilibrium
you take some income from A and give it to B, loss of utility of A will outweigh
the utility gain of B (because marginal utility is decreasing) and thus
obviously total utility will be less in any situation where income is not fully
equally distributed.
My students
then asked how I can justify concern with inequality if I reject the welfarist
view which is the main ideological vehicle through which equality of outcomes
is being justified. (A non-utilitarian, contractarian alternative is provided
by Rawls. Yet another alternative, based on equal capabilities—a close cousin
to equality of opportunity (of which more below) is provided by Amartya Sen.)
My answer
was that I justify concern with income inequality on three grounds.
The first ground is instrumental: the effect on economic growth. After the period of the 1990s where, due to lack of data, we ended up with inconclusive results on the link between inequality and economic growth, we are having more and more evidence that high levels of inequality slow down the increase in total income. We are able to show that now because we have access to micro data and a much more sophisticated view of both inequality and growth. Here, as examples, are the papers by Sarah Voitchovsky and by Roy van der Weide and myself. But, it has to be acknowledged: if empirical literature were to come to a different conclusion, namely that inequality helps growth we should have to drop that instrumental argument against high inequality.
The second
is political effect. In societies where economic and political spheres are not separated by the Chinese wall
(and all existing societies are such), inequality in economic power seeps and
ultimately invades and conquers the political sphere. Instead of one-person
one-vote democracy we get one-dollar one-vote plutocracy. This outcome appears inevitable,
especially in modern societies where running political campaigns is extremely
expensive. But it was not very different in ancient Greece or Rome. if we hold
that democracy, a more or less equal influence of everyone on public affairs,
is a good thing, we have to be in favor of severe limits on income and wealth inequality.
It seems to me that the negative impact of inequality on democracy, not only obvious
only in theory, is now being confirmed empirically as well (see Martin Giddens’
“Affluence and Influence”).
Let me note parenthetically
that even if we failed to detect such explicit influence of the rich on policy
making, the a priori case that it must exist (but is difficult to measure) would
still be extremely strong. Because for the opposite case to hold, i.e., rich
people give money to politicians but do not get anything in return, we have to
assume an entirely irrational behavior of the rich: they throw money away for
no reason. That goes so much against the fundamentals of economics that if we
assume it here we should also assume it that when people (say) go to
restaurants; they throw money randomly: “Your glass of wine costs $10. Well, I
will give you $15 and you do not need to give me the wine”. If that behavior seems
reasonable to you, then I would agree that the rich may not influence politicians
to whom they give money.
The third
ground is philosophical. As Rawls has argued, every departure from unequal
distribution of resources has to be defended by an appeal to a higher
principle. Because we are all equal individuals (whether as declared by the Universal
Charter of Human Rights or by God), we should all have an approximately equal
opportunity to develop our skills and to lead a “good (and pleasant) life”.
Because inequality of income almost directly translates into inequality of opportunities,
it also directly negates that fundamental equality of all humans. This is I think pretty evident on an a priori
basis, but we have also an increasing number of papers that show the positive
correlation between inequality of income and inequality of opportunity (see Marrero
and Rodriguez, Miles Corak). Families with greater income ensure that their
children have much better opportunities (which negates the fundamental equality
of which we spoke) and in turn make sure they this new inequality of opportunity
is converted into yet higher income for themselves
and their own children. So, a positive feedback works very strongly to maintain
unequal access to opportunities.
I have to
say here that in addition inequality of opportunity affects negatively economic
growth (so we now have a negative effect going from my third ground back to the
first) which makes inequality of opportunity abhorrent on two grounds: (1) it negates
fundamental human equality, and (2) it lowers the pace of material improvements
for society.
My argument,
if I need to reiterate it, is: you can reject welfarism, hold that inter-personal
comparison of utility is impossible, and still feel very strongly that economic
outcomes should be made more equal—that inequality should be limited so that it
does not strongly affect opportunities, so that it does not slow growth and so
that it does not undermine democracy. Isn’t that enough?
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.