In a recent article
published here (which is a prequel to his book), Professor Harry G. Frankfurt takes a philosophic position
against our concern with inequality. According to him, our intuition does tell us that we should
be worried about inequality, but that intuition is misleading for an effective
moral theory where we should be only concerned about our own well-being and “good
life”, not in relationship to the others. He allows however that we should be
concerned with incomes of those whose “resources are too little.”
I have
already encountered similar opinions, among economists, and written about that (here), so it is with some reluctance that I have to cover the same ground
again. But I must admit that this kind of argument is somewhat of a red flag
to me so here I go again. For simplicity, I divide my argument into three
parts.
We are social beings. It was stated by Adam Smith very nicely
that our needs vary in function of what we consider to be socially acceptable. In
a much quoted passage, Smith contrasts a man living in a relatively poor society
who is content with a roughly-hewn shirt and another one, living in a richer society,
who would be ashamed to be seen in public
without a linen shirt. Smith was drawing on his own experience, having observed
how what is socially acceptable, i.e., what are our “needs”, has changed in his
own lifetime as England and Scotland had become richer.
Here is the
quote:
“[Under
necessities] I understand not only the commodities that are indispensable for
the support of life, but whatever the custom of the country renders it indecent
for creditable people, even of the lowest order, to be without.” (Book 5,
Chapter 2)
Smith’s observation
has far-reaching consequences. If our needs depend on what is socially
acceptable, then they will clearly vary as between different societies. They will
depend on the wealth of such societies or wealth of our peer groups. Consequently,
our needs are (1) even in theory endless (because development has no material limit),
and (2) they are thoroughly relative. We cannot distinguish between that part of
the needs which is presumably due to ourselves, our “real” needs that, according
to Professor Frankfurt, determine whether “[we] have good lives, and not how
[our] lives compare with the lives of others” and the other part which is presumably due to the
environment.
It is
futile to try to distinguish between the two. We do not know what are our needs
until we live in a society and observe the needs of others. So, pace Professor Frankfurt, we cannot just
imagine that others do not exist as he enjoins us to do. All our needs are
social.
But my friend
Carla Yumatle, in a discussion on Twitter, has made a point against this interpretation
(I paraphrase her): yes, all our needs may be social, but it does not mean that
a moral theory, whose objective is to provide us with some moral guidance, needs
to take this into account. Actually, it may deplore that we have such needs.
Carla draws the distinction between
Rousseau’s amour propre (which is
basically vanity, or what used to be called “pride” or self-love in
relationship to others) and amour de soi
(which is concern with ourselves as such). The latter would be, if I understand
her well, acceptable, according to Frankfurt, but the former (which obviously
relies on our comparisons with others) would not.
Authenticity. But that too depends on a false dichotomy between amour de soi and amour propre. The two are indistinguishable. To show that they are different
we have to prove somehow that only amour
de soi is authentic, while amour propre
is not. Or as Professor Frankfurt claims: “It [concern with inequality] leads
a person away from understanding what he himself truly [sic!] requires in order
to pursue his own most authentic needs, interests, and ambitions.”
But similarly
to the previous argument, here too we cannot tell what are authentic and unauthentic needs. I really have
no idea what are my authentic needs as compared to the needs that I develop
from living in New York. If I lived in Belgrade (as I did) or Chennai (as I did
not), I would have had entirely different needs. Does anyone doubt that? So
what are my “authentic” needs?
Do I have an
“authentic” need for an iPhone? No, I did not have an “authentic” need so long as
iPhones did not exist. But now I do have an “authentic” need for an iPhone. However much we might like the fact that
somebody decides not to own an iPhone when everybody else has it, we cannot
claim that she is more authentic or somehow unconcerned with her relative
position. She might decide not to have an
iPhone because she does not like to talk on the phone or because she likes to be
contrarian but there is nothing more authentic in rejecting to follow the crowd
than in deciding to go with it. We might like those who reject crowd-behavior
or even admire them, but they are not by any means more “authentic” than the rest.
Welfare function. Finally, an economic argument is that once we allow for our
concern with the poor to enter our utility function, as Professor Frankfurt tells
us to do, there is nothing to stop us from introducing in that same utility function our concern with incomes of those who are richer
than ourselves.
Moreover, if
Professor Frankfurt keeps on insisting that despite all we should be concerned only with incomes of the poor, neither Professor
Frankfurt nor anybody else can tell us what is that income at which we should
begin to worry about other human beings whose “resources are too little”. He cannot
tell us what this “too little” is. Does he want us to be concerned only with incomes
of those who live below 1 international dollar per day, or those below $5, or those
below $15? If it is only those below the absolute poverty threshold ($1 per day
per capita), then we should not be concerned with poverty in the US at all because
nobody lives below that level. Is this okay with Professor Frankfurt?
But if Professor
Frankfurt wants us to be concerned with poverty in the US, then he is introducing
precisely the relative poverty measure, that is the poverty which varies with income level of a society where we
live, a concept which he has banished before under the guise of not being “authentic”.
So, his
reasoning brings him back to the beginning where he is unable to define needs
as separate from the context where they are expressed. He is unable to do so because he is unable to distinguish
between the so-called “authentic” needs and those that we develop simply by living
in a society from the very moment when we are born. We cannot define what the "good life" is independently of the others.
So, his whole edifice crumbles.
So, his whole edifice crumbles.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.