Working on global inequality makes you ask questions you
would never ask otherwise simply because they would not occur to you. It is like
going from a two-dimensional world to a three-dimensional: even the familiar suddenly
appears unusual.
Take the convergence economics. In theory of growth
convergence indicates the regularity that poorer countries tend to grow faster
than richer countries because they can use all the knowledge and innovations
that the richer have already produced. Simply put, when you are at the technological
frontier, you need to invent something new all the time and you may grow at say,
1 or 1.5 percent per year. When you are below the frontier, you can copy and
grow at the higher rate. (Of course, economists talk of “conditional convergence”
because the theory assumes that all other factors, that in reality differ
between the rich and poor countries, are the same.) Nevertheless, there is some
evidence for conditional convergence in empirical studies and it is, for obvious
reasons, considered a good thing.
Now, when you look more closely you realize that convergence
is studied in terms of countries but in reality it deals with the convergence in
living standards between individuals.
We express it in terms of a poorer country catching up with the richer because we
are used to doing our economics in terms of nation-states and implicitly assume
that there is no movement of people between countries. But in reality convergence
is nothing else but the diminution of income inequality between all individuals
in the world.
So, how best to achieve such a decrease in inequality between
people? Economic theory, common sense and simulation exercises clearly show
that it can be best done by allowing free movement of people. Such a policy
would increase global income (as any free movement of factors of production in principle
should), reduce global poverty and global inequality. It is immaterial, from a
global perspective, that it might slower between-country convergence (as some recent results for
EU indicate) because countries are, as we have just seen, not the relevant entities
in global economics: the relevant entities are individuals and their welfare
levels. If people’s incomes are more equal, it is wholly immaterial if the gap between
the average incomes in A and B increases. To see this point, think in the familiar terms
of the nation-state: no one in his or her right mind would argue that people
from the Appalachian in the US should not be allowed to move to California
because the average income in the Appalachia might go down. In fact, both the
average income in California and in Appalachia might go down, and both inequalities
in the Appalachia and California might go up, and yet the overall US income
would rise and US inequality would be less.
The argument is identical for the world as a whole: a high-skilled
Nigerian who moves to the United States might lower the mean income of Nigeria
(and might also lower the mean income of the US), and might in addition cause both
inequalities to go up, and yet the global GDP would be greater and global inequality
would be less. In short, the world would be a better place. The objections to
migration, namely that it might reduce the average income in recipient
countries, raised by Paul Collier in his
book “Exodus” are immaterial because the real subject of our analysis is not
the nation-state but the individual.
Thus far the argument seems to me entirely incontestable. But
then things get a bit messier. Pushing this logic further, and using the
results of the Gallup poll
that show the percentage of people who desire to move out of their countries,
we find that in the case of unimpeded global migration some countries could
lose up to 90 percent of their populations. They may cease to exist: everybody
but a few thousand people might move out. Even the few who might at first
remain, could soon find their lives
there intolerable, not least because providing public goods for a very small
population may be exceedingly expensive.
So, what?—it could be asked. If Chad, Liberia and Mauritania
cease to exist because everybody wants to move to Italy and France, why should
one be concerned: people have freely chosen to be better off in Italy and
France, and that’s all there is to that. But then, it could be asked, would not
disappearance of countries also mean disappearance of distinct cultures, languages
and religions? Yes, but if people do not care about these cultures, languages
and religions, why should they be maintained?
Destroying the variety of human traditions is not costless, and
I can see that one might believe that maintaining variety of languages and
cultures is not less important that maintaining variety of the flora and fauna
in the world, but I wonder who needs to bear the cost of that. Should people in
Mali be forced to live in Mali because somebody in London thinks that some variety
of human existence would be lost if they all came to England? I am not wholly
insensitive to this argument, but I think that it would be more honest to say openly
that the cost of maintaining this “worldwide heritage” is borne not by those
who defend it in theory but by those in Mali who are not allowed to move out.
There is a clear trade-off between the maintenance of
diversity of cultural traditions and freedom of individuals to do as they please.
I would be happier if the trade-off did
not exist, but it does. And if I have to choose between the two, I would choose
human freedom even if it means loss of tradition. After all, are traditions
that no one cares about worth preserving? The world has lost Marcomanni, Quadi,
Sarmatians, Visigoths, Alans, Vandals, Avars and thousands others. They have disappeared together with their languages,
cultures and traditions. Do we really miss them today?
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.