As I was writing the 3rd chapter of my new book
which deals with the change in the factors underlying global inequality (from
being driven by within-national inequalities to being driven by between-national
inequalities, and perhaps in the future, going back to within- inequalities), entitled
“From Karl Marx to Frantz Fanon and then back to Marx?”, I decided that I should
reread some of Fanon.
A couple of days ago, in Washington, I found my 1973 copy of
Croatian-Serbian translation (with a very nice postscript by the Croatian/Yugoslav sociologist Vjekoslav Mikecin) of “Les
damnés de la terre” which I read probably in 1974 or 1975. Now I reread basically
only my notes, and as in 1975, I skipped the last chapter on the psychological effects
of violence (Fanon was a psychiatrist).
What are my impressions, reading now a book published at the
height of decolonization and when the income gap between the First and the Third World
was at its peak, in 1961? First, I noticed how much the world has changed.
Fanon was one of the “prophets” of the Third World. Well, neither the Third,
nor the Second, worlds exist anymore. He spoke of colonies in Africa. None exists
today. He spoke of Western left-wing Marxist intelligentsia. It is all gone. Even
the copy of the book I held in my hands added to this eerie feeling. It was published
in Yugoslavia, which no longer exists. It was published in Croato-Serbian, the language
which (at least under that name) no longer exists. Did everything he wrote
about disappear?
What can we say about Fanon today? I divide my impression under
three headings: violence, new man and economics.
Violence. Fanon is perhaps best known for his
support of violence used by movements for national liberation. He never glorified violence like Sorel and many
Europeans writers who glorified World War I (or people who today read books
like “An American sniper”). But he thought that violence was necessary to fight
the colonizers: “eye for an eye, tooth for a tooth”, knife for a knife, gun for
a gun. Was he right? In some sense yes. There is no doubt, I think, that in
Vietnam, Algeria, Angola, Zimbabwe, Burma, Kenya, the colonizers never wanted to
give up power. They were the first to use violence and national liberation
movements had to do the same. Moreover, the violence used by the weaker side is
not the same as the violence used by the stronger side.
But Fanon’s language is not guarded. Although I think that
his Chapter 1, “On violence”, is the most interesting part of the book (perhaps
the only one that he really finished; the book was published posthumously), he
seems at times to view violence as a “cleansing tool”, to believe that there is
something valuable in it as such, and not to realize that once it ceases to be
used carefully and in very controlled and instrumental doses, it turns against
the one who uses it. This was indeed often the history of the newly independent
countries; many have descended into infernal cycles of violence: civil wars in
Algeria, Nigeria, Ivory Coast, Sudan; permanent wars in Congo, numerous coups
d’etat.
New man. In Chapter 2 especially, but throughout
the book as well, Fanon insists on Africa rejecting (1) colonizers, (2) capitalism,
(3) domestic small bourgeoisie often allied with the colonizers, and (4) a return
to a romanticized African past. He believes that the objective of the national
struggle should be the creation of a “new man” or a new society. This was a
common belief of all revolutionary movements throughout most of the 20th
century. They have not achieved much. “The
new man” has remained elusive. Often the quest has led to tyrannies. And indeed
Fanon gives us almost no guidance about how this “new man” and new society are to
be created, other than identifying (like
Mao before him) in peasantry the truly revolutionary class. But while Marx explains,
at least in theory, why the proletariat might produce this “new man”—because the
condition for its own liberation is the liberation of the entire society—Fanon does
not explain much at all.
Economics. Fanon does not spend much time on
economics (a common feature among Marxisant authors of the 1960s). He obviously
rejects capitalism, but rejects also state ownership of the means of production
because it would simply lead to state officials taking positions of authority.
He is in favor of the nationalization of the tertiary sector (services). Interestingly,
he regards control of trade as crucial: perhaps it itself is a reflection
of Africa’s backwardness.
Fanon seems, in two comments that he makes on the matter, in
favor of democratic ownership of capital, perhaps similar to “self-management”
or “market socialism” that existed in Yugoslavia. That sounds good because
indeed the internal organization of such enterprises was much more democratic
than the organization of similar enterprises under capitalism. But (perhaps unfortunately)
history seems to have taught us that people work harder under dictatorship in the
workplace, and are content to let democracy exist only in public (but not work)
sphere. Thus worker-controlled enterprises tended to waste capital, make bad
investment decision, prefer to distribute income in wages, never fire anyone
and not require workers to put in much effort. As every Marxist would tell you,
if you are economically inefficient, you are “toast.”
So Fanon’s preferred economic formula would have also failed,
and indeed it failed, not only in Yugoslavia, but also elsewhere it was tried: in
Zambia, Tanzania and Algeria. It could be even argued that countries that kept
state ownership like Vietnam and China did better. Fanon perhaps did not know
the comment attributed to Bela Kun during the 1919 Hungarian Soviet revolution
that “workers will die for the revolution, but will not work for it.”
Fanon is ferocious in his critique of inability of the local Third
World bourgeoisies to save, innovate, create any value, and go beyond their
role of “cocktail party organizers for the Western bourgeoisie”. He writes: “the national
bourgeoisie will take the role of foreman of European companies and will
practically convert the county into a brothel”. These pages in Chapter 3 (“The problems of national
consciousness”) are very powerful and could have been written today. The problem
however is that, when you start with low income and have little education and
knowledge, and with little or nothing to
offer to the rest of the world, you really cannot be more than “a foreman” or a
“brothel.” Regardless of what you would like to be.
Et alors? Thus, melancholically, I have to conclude that Fanon was often wrong
on all three (important) topics. But being
wrong is not a good reason for not being read. Fanon remains, I think, one of the best
sources for the period of decolonization. This is a period which is (self-satisfactorily)
ignored today, so much so that Obama, US president whose own father fought for independence
of Kenya and whose grandfather was jailed and tortured by the British, could in
his long and wide-ranging speech on world history
in the 20th century avoid to mention any names or
countries linked with the struggle for independence except for a few anodyne
comments on Nelson Mandela. Thus, no Vietnam, no Algeria, no Zambia, no Ghana,
no Indonesia, no Kenya, no Tanzania, no Egypt. No… Well, if you are satisfied
with such a truncated history of the past half century, then you should ignore
Fanon too.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.