Today I read
an article on shortages and economic collapse in Venezuela. The reason why
there are huge lines in front of the stores was the same known to any student
of socialist economies: state stores sell heavily subsidized goods and the
demand for such goods exceeds their supply. Then, many people buy much more
than they need and engage in selling the goods at higher prices to those who
are either sufficiently rich to pay higher prices or who have been unlucky that
the supply ended before their turn came.
The buyers
and resellers of such goods in Venezuela are called, according to the New York
Times, bachaqueros. Ricardo Hausmann,
from the Kennedy School at Harvard who was Venezuela’s planning minister in the
1990 was then quoted
by the New York Times as saying: “This is the crazy thing about the system.
A lot of people are putting in effort [to buy the goods and resell them], and
none of that increases the supply of anything. This is perfectly unproductive
labor”.
That statement
made me stop. “Perfectly unproductive labor”? But that “unproductive labor”, as
every economist knows, improves the allocation of goods. The goods flow toward
those who have greater ability to pay and since we tend to associate greater
ability to pay with greater utility, the goods, thanks to bachaqueros’ activities,
are better allocated. If one argues that bachaqueros activity is unproductive
because it “does not increase the supply of anything” then one should argue
that the activity of any trade or intermediation is unproductive because it
does not produce new goods, but simple reallocates. The same argument could be
used for the entire financial sector, starting with Wall Street. The entire activity
of Wall Street has not produced a single pound of flour, a single loaf of bread
or a single sofa. But why we believe that financial intermediation is
productive is that it allows money to flow from the places where it would be
less efficiently used to the places where it would be used more efficiently. Or
for that matter from the consumers who cannot pay much to the consumers who
can. Exactly the activity done by bachaqueros.
Hausmann’s
view is identical to the (falsely) Marxist view of productive and unproductive activities
reflected in socialist countries’ national accounts, called Material Net Product.
Socialist countries’ approach was that all services (including health, education
and government administration) were unproductive because they did not produce
new physical goods. Obviously, speculators like bachaqueros were the very epitome
of unproductive, and even (it was held) “socially noxious” or “abhorrent” labor.
This view had practical consequences for the calculation of national income because
the level of national income in socialist countries was underestimated, compared
to what it would be according to the UN’s System of National Accounts, but the
rate of growth was overestimated because productivity increases were generally
greater in production of goods than in services.
Marx had a distinction
between productive and unproductive labor which was more sophisticated.
Productive was all labor that resulted in the production of the surplus value.
Thus, Marx in a well-known example, shows that a singer (a prototype of activity
that does not produce anything tangible) is engaged in productive labor so long
as he is hired by a company or an individual and creates profit for his
employer. In Marx’s view productive-unproductive dichotomy was not given forever
but changed depending on socio-economic formation. The problem with socialist governments
in Eastern Europe was that they had trouble deciding what should be productive
and unproductive according to Marx in a socialist society and took the easy
road to declare unproductive whatever activity did not produce tangible physical
goods.
There was
also a categorization introduced by Ann
Krueger in the 1970s who defined the so-called “directly unproductive activities”
or “rent-seeking activities”. The idea was to classify under such heading all activities
whose objective is to extract some government concession that would result in
higher incomes for those successful in
lobbying. Pharmaceutical and IT companies that pay hundreds of K Street lobbyists
in Washington today would fall under that category—even if Krueger’s
classification was originally intended mostly to push developing countries’
governments to be less interventionist (was directed especially against “India’s
Licence Raj”; see Bhagwati
here). Lobbying was, it was argued, unproductive because it led to the creation
of rents. And rent is, of course, an income that can be taken away without
affecting the supply and allocation of goods.
Finally, it
leads us to the topic of theft. It is not easy to put theft in its right place
in economics. Theft for private use can be justified by arguing that the bread
stolen by a poor person from a rich one is almost certain to increase the amount of “social happiness”.
(I have often thought of that in New York where that the old-fashioned idea that
one should keep $20 in his/her wallet to give it to a mugger certainly made
sense in helping "the greatest happiness for the greatest numbers"). The issue is
more complicated when we come to theft for resale: burglary of a jewelry store
and resale of the jewels might increase overall welfare if burglars are very poor
and jewelry owner very rich but it cannot be defended on better allocation grounds
because the jewels could have been equally accessible to those who wanted to
buy them whether they are sold by the owner or by thieves.
The issue of
preventing theft leads us to yet another category of labor that can also be
considered unproductive: security personnel or what is called the “guard labor”. Their salaries are paid in order to prevent
theft. They clearly do not increase the supply of goods, nor do they improve goods’
allocation. The only defense that their
labor does produce something is in the argument that prevention of theft improves
protection of property which makes for more investments and increases long-term
growth. But this is, as can be seen, a
rather more convoluted justification, which by the way, can be also used to argue
why theft, even if it might improve short-term welfare, is likely to be pernicious
in the longer-term, a point of view that goes back to Adam Smith.
Deciding for
a capitalist economy what is productive and what is unproductive labor is not always
easy. How much more difficult if we study economic history: how to classify
monks and priests when they are paid by legally compulsory tithes; Robin Hood
could be defended on the maximization of utility principle but criticized as
inimical to long-term growth; Francis Drake stole goods owned by the Spaniards who
extracted them by using forced labor…
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.