I have reviewed Francis Fukuyama’s The Origins of
Political Order (OPO) here
and here,
and I could have written at least two additional reviews. It is a great book in
many respects. Its sequel Political
Order and Political Decay (POPD) is less so. It is a very good book but in its overarching essential idea and originality of discussion it is not
at the level of its predecessor.
Technically, POPD has two objectives: first, to continue with
the exposition of how the three pillars of good governance (strong state, rule
of law and accountability) have been created in various parts of the world from
the Industrial Revolution to today, that is to continue with the line of
discussion from OPO which ended at the time of the Industrial Revolution; and second, to look at the causes of political
decay (institutional rigidity and repatrimonization). The first objective is
much less clearly achieved than in the previous book: the country stories,
while interesting, are hardly new and it is not always clear if they were truly
necessary to highlight a given idea. The
second objective is discussed practically only in the last part of the book
with reference to the United States.
I have to start the review with some negatives. The
historical episodes that are discussed, at times with verve, are unfortunately also
often somewhat cliché-ed. The capsule version of histories of Greece, Southern Italy,
Nigeria, and Argentina resemble Wikipedia summaries which are useful if you
want to learn history of a given country in ten pages, but otherwise neither new nor exciting. Moreover, just a couple of paragraphs (rather than the capsule version of
history) would have been enough to
provide examples the author needs. The book is thus unnecessarily long (more
than 600 pages) and at times seems to consist of notes that an author
takes from his readings in order to use them later in his own book. (Yes, some people do read Grundrisse, but do we need every writer’s Grundrisse
pasted in his book?)
Lots of that unnecessary length is also due to quasi verbatim
repetitions of certain points. I found these word for word repetitions rather
annoying because they seem to be somewhat condescending to the reader. Early on
Fukuyama makes a very interesting and important point that countries that
democratize too early before a strong civil service has been created, almost
inevitably develop clientilistic politics. He uses, among others, the examples
of Germany (democracy after civil service) and Italy and Greece (the reverse)
to illustrate his point. But then repeats this at least twenty times in the following
chapters. One grows a bit tired of this repetition. Moreover, it is only on page
201 that we learn that the original idea about the sequencing of civil service
and democracy belongs to Martin Shefter. I was thus left under the impression
that no one, including possibly even the author, has read the book—as a book—from
page 1 to page 609, because such copy-and-paste repetitions would have been
deleted.
Let’s now move to substantive points.
I found Fukuyama’s discussion of clientelism illuminating. He
considers clientelism as a kind of proto-accountability. Full accountability of
the rulers implies the existence of democracy and an impersonal
(non-patrimonial) state. But short of that ideal, clientelism nevertheless imposes
constraints on political leaders because they have to deliver “goods” to the
electorate or more exactly to their voters. Fukuyama uses, in addition to the
already mentioned Greece and Southern Italy, US in the 19th century (after
Andrew Jackson) as a prototype of a clientilistic state. It was the Progressive
Era in the 1920s and then FDR that managed to create a more impersonal civil
service, even if never to the extent that it existed in advanced European
countries. But currently the US is sliding, or even rushing, toward repatrimonization
(I will address this later).
Another important point is Fukuyama’s disagreement with the
idea of “extractive institutions” allegedly inherited from colonialism (Acemoglu
and Robinson) and with geographical determinism (Engelman ad Sokoloff). Both
are fundamentally the same: “While Acemoglu and Robinson criticize what they characterize as economic determinism of
writers such as Sachs and Diamond, and point to good institutions as the cause
of development, they nonetheless trace the origin of institutions in turn to conditions
of climate and geography.” (p. 235). Fukuyama’s disagreement is most clearly
stated in the case of Africa where the European legacy is not “extractive institutions”
but no institutions at all (p. 392); but in Latin America too, Argentina and
Costa Rica illustrate the development paths that are exactly at the opposite of
what geo-institutionalists would expect.
The last part of the book (some 100 pages) is dedicated to
the decay of political institutions in the United States. It is important to underline
that the book was written before Trump, so facile ascription of all evils to
Trump and “populism” which is the bread-and-butter of political scientists
today does not apply here. Problems that Fukuyama uncovers go much deeper than
Trump. They are of four kinds.
The fist two are judicialization of the legislative function and
adversarial legalism whereby normal legislative functions of a parliament (Congress
in the US) are delegated to courts. It is through legal process that individuals,
NGO and lobbyists decide what is the public interest. The shift towards many of the
decisions being taken through the legal process (rather than a vote of
representatives) might seem at first to be more democratic or participative
until one realizes that the public interest is then left to be defined by
whoever has most resources to pursue expensive legal suits or most patience to
do so. Thus both lobbyists and NGOs come for criticism. And the legislature as
well which has abdicated its natural role to define what is the public interest
and is in the process of returning the US to being the country of “courts and parties”
that it used to be in the 19th century.
The third is the “gift exchange” which is the essence of
lobbyism and the core of the influence of private interest on government. Since
the “gift exchange” (say, high paying job in the private sector for a former “friendly”
politician) is not an immediate quid pro quo, but is delayed in time, it does
not fall under the category of bribery although it fundamentally is.
The last is vetocracy or the existence of too many veto
players which makes political decision-making very difficult or totally stalled.
While the first three ills are examples of political decay due to repatrimonization,
the last one is an example of decay due to institutional rigidity: “Americans
regard their Constitution as a quasi-religious document, so get them to rethink
its most basic tenets would be an uphill struggle” (p. 505).
In the Afterword written in 2015, Fukuyama responds to the critics
who found his views of the US political system too harsh. It seems, on the
contrary, in the light of what has transpired since 2015, that Fukuyama’s views
have been rather confirmed.
Despite book’s problems (which could have been fixed by a
good editor), and the fact that it is a less incisive book than its predecessor,
POPD is still an excellent book, definitely worth reading. At times, after a
few paragraphs that seem to come straight from one of the boilerplate Obama speeches,
and with one’s attention flagging, there is suddenly a brilliant sentence that displays
the magic of an erudite thinker. It is like Maradona lulling his opponents to
sleep just in order to strike a more improbable goal.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.