I mentioned in my last post in which I reviewed Francis Fukuyama’s excellent “The origins of political order” that in my next post I will
present some further comments on the book. (The first post was mostly a summary
of the book’s key points.)
But as I was taking notes of the book—a thing I have
been doing for many years after finishing good books—I noticed among my notes a
number of Fukuyama’s views on economics, many directy critical of some mainstream
nostrums. Because I think that few economists have read Fukuyama, and perhaps even fewer have read him attentively, and perhaps
even fewer have read the entire book, I decided to bring up Fukuyama’s several economic
statements, with only minimal commentary from me.
Against “property rights fetishism” (Fukuyama’s term)
“The
theory that links the different components of the rule of law to economic
growth is empirically questionable and becomes doubly so when projected back
onto societies that existed under Malthusian economic conditions” (p. 247).
“In
a Malthusian economy where intensive growth is not possible, strong property
rights simply reinforce the existing distribution of resources. The actual
distribution of wealth is more likely to represent chance starting conditions
or the property holders access to political power than productivity or hard
work….rigid defenders of property rights often forget that the existing
distribution of wealth does not always reflect the superior virtue of the
wealthy and that markets are not always efficient” (p 142).
At the end of the book, Fukuyama, when discussing the
contemporary China, writes that “good enough” rule of law is often sufficient
for fast economic growth. Moreover, technology is much more important than
property rights. Fukuyama points out that in a Malthusian world, no property
rights will provide you with an economic surplus; but technological development will
(p. 249).
These comments are quite clearly a critique of the
views propounded by Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson in, among other works,
“Why Nations Fail” (the book was published after Fukuyama’s “The origins...”); but
also of a number of economists who in a Whiggish type of history-writing consider
the protection of property rights as almost a sole, or a sufficient, factor needed
to ensure economic growth. Economic historians have generally been much less convinced of that.
Against Hayek
In several sections of the book, Fukuyama criticizes
Hayek’s ahistoricism, that is, the assumption, frequently stated in Hayek’s work
(including in “Law, Legislation and Liberty”), that the English Common Law
emerged entirely through “spontaneous” decentralized coordination. This is rejected by Fukuyama, who argues that without a strong state Common Law would
have never come into existence.
Here is the key point:
“Hayek
was simply wrong about certain of his historical facts” (p. 254). “The later
evolution of the Common Law might have been a spontaneous process, but its existence
as a framework for legal decision-making required centralized political power
to bring it into being” (p. 258).
And also,
“This
is the point that Hayek and his libertarian followers fail to see: the Common
Law may be the work of dispersed judges, but it would not have come into being
in the first place…without a strong centralized state” (p. 260).
The same thing is repeated, almost verbatim, on p.
253.
In the last section of the book, there is yet another
critique of Hayek. Pace Hayek, large
scale designs sometimes do work, writes Fukuyama (p. 446). In other words,
“constructivism” is not bound to fail every time.
Against Mancur Olson
Fukuyama also disagrees with Mancur Olson. The
critique is made in the context of the discussion that tries to explain why Chinese
absolutism that was neither constrained by the rule of law nor accountability, imposed
only very limited taxes on citizenry. (This was also discussed recently by
Debin Ma in his “Rock, Scissors,
Paper”.) Fukuyama gives several reasons, including difficulties of
delegation and control over an extensive domain, “satisficing” rather than
maximizing behavior etc.
I am not sure however if his critique of Olson is
justified because in Olson’s model, Chinese emperors are “stationary bandits”;
hence they have an “all-encompassing interest” and are not indifferent to the
wealth of the realm. It is then possible that the tax rates they applied did not
attempt to maximize own revenue.
Here is Fukuyama:
“The
only problem with Olson´s theory is that isn’t correct. The rulers of
traditional agrarian societies often failed to tax their subjects at anything
close to Olson´s posited maximizing rate” (p. 304).
“Olson´s
assumption that any ruler would want to maximize revenues reflects the common
assumption of modern economics that maximization is a universal characteristic
of human behavior. But this is an anachronistic projection of modern values
backward onto a society that did not necessarily share them” (p. 306).
Against the rational choice model
The last sentence could also be read as a link with
the next critique: that of a rational homo economicus. Fukuyama’s argument is
that humans are social beings; they never existed in a presocial state, and
cooperation is not merely the product of them figuring out whether they are in
some cases better off cooperating than not. Coperation, Fukuyama seems to say,
is “hard-wired” since humans were always “social animals”. (This argument is consistent
with Fukuyama’s emphasis on “patrimonialization”, or tribalism, as a defining feature
of most historical political orders.)
“..a
rational choice model of collective action in which individuals calculate that
they will be better off by cooperating with one another, vastly understates the
degree of social cooperation that exists in human societies and misunderstands
the motives that underlie it” (p. 439).
And again, a few pages later:
“rational
self-interest is wholly inadequate in explaining the degree of social
cooperation” (p. 442).
Against Amartya Sen
Just one sentence here, to say that current Indian
democracy is not based on a history of democracy in Indian states but on the
fact that the fragmented Indian polity, with the “checks and balances” exercised
by the Brahmins over the rulers never allowed for the rise of absolutism. There
was no history of democracy in India; but, importantly, there never was a
social basis for tyranny.
“This
is a very superficial view of contemporary Indian politics. It is not that
democracy in its modern institutional manifestations is deeply rooted in
ancient Indian practices, as observers like Amartya Sen have suggested. Rather
the course of Indian political development demonstrates that there never was the
social basis for development of a
tyrannical state that could concentrate power, to reach deeply into society and
change its fundamental social institutions” (p. 187).
I am not sure that on this point Fukuyama and Amartya
Sen are so far apart as the statement implies—but I may be wrong.
At the end, another concept that I really liked, handsomly-termed,
“the iron law of latifundia” or large
real estates: “the rich tend to get richer in the absence of state
intervention” (p. 368)
Fukuyama by these statements surely calls on the economists
to rethink some of their cherished ideas. And to ask: do such ideas work only
now, but not in history; do they work only on paper, but not in real life?
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.