[I am publishing early and somewhat
modified versions of self-contained sections from my forthcoming book “Capitalism, alone”,
Harvard UP, hopefully 2019. They may be a bit longer than my usual posts. This
is the first such piece. All comments are welcome]
China is not the West. But what
exactly is the difference, in the long-term context, between China and the
West? This is a huge question that has recently (by recent, I mean the past two
decades) acquired additional importance due to the rise of China, its contrast with
the West in terms of the organization of its economy, and much better historical data we now have.
Here I would like to make use of an interesting take on that issue made by
Giovanni Arrighi in his Adam Smith in Beijing: Lineages of the Twenty-First Century.
Arrighi starts from a dichotomy that
I think he was the first to have defined in a series of articles, between
Smithian “natural” path of development of capitalism and Marx’s “unnatural”
(the term is Arrigihi’s) path. Smith’s natural path, “the natural progress of
opulence” in the terminology of The Wealth
of Nations, is that of a market economy of small producers that grows,
through division of labor, from agriculture into manufacturing and only later goes
into domestic trade and eventually into long-distance foreign trade. The path is
“natural” because it follows our needs (from food to textiles to trade, from
village community to town to faraway lands) and thus does not jump over the
stages. Throughout—Smith is careful to mention—the state lets market economy
and capitalists thrive, protects property and imposes tolerable taxes but does maintain
its relative autonomy when it comes to economic and foreign policy. (This is
why, in one part of The Wealth of Nation
Smith praises The Navigation Act, entirely based on the argument of national
security while in the other part of the Wealth
of Nations, perhaps having forgotten that he praised it, he savages it on
the grounds of monopoly.)
Arrighi summarizes it thus: “The
Smithian features…[are] the gradualism of reforms and state action aimed at
expanding and upgrading social division of labor; the huge expansion of
education; the subordination of capitalist interest to the national interest
and the active encouragement of inter-capitalist competition” (p. 361).
Marx’s approach in contrast was that
he took what he observed in Europe in his time to be a “normal capitalist
path”. But what Marx thought of “normal” was a system which, in Smith’s words
applied to Holland, (1) inverted the natural progress by developing commerce
first and agriculture last, a system that was thus ”unnatural and retrograde”
and where (2) the state had lost its autonomy to the bourgeoisie.
In fact, capitalist interests became
dominant in running the states in the West, from Marx’s time all the way to today,
both when it comes to economics (think of the tax cuts under Trump) or foreign
policy (think of the Iraq war profiteering). Capitalists took over the state
and, famously as Marx wrote, the government became “a committee to manage the common
affairs of the bourgeoisie.” Such a path inverted Smithian “natural”
development, by jumping the stages and going into long-distance trade and
colonialism before it laboriously and sufficiently developed local production. Most
importantly, however, Marxian path differs from the Smithian in that there is
no state autonomy vis-à-vis bourgeoisie. Since European capitalists thrived in conditions
of conquest, slavery and colonialism, they needed the state for such an
“excentic” development, that is, for the projection of power abroad, and thus
had to “conquer” it. This made the European path aggressive and warlike.
Arrighi believes that what we hold today
to be a standard capitalist path is the
one described by Marx. (Peer Vries in his excellent “Escaping
poverty” defines
capitalism as rational profit seeking
plus commodification of labor plus
projection of power outside.) But that path was specific to Europe and cannot
be generalized or “deified”. An alternative path, much closer to Smithian, was followed
by China, from Song to Qing dynasties. There, market economy was even more
developed than in Western Europe (probably until about 1500) but commercial interests
were never able to organize themselves sufficiently so that they could come even
close to dictating state policy. The authoritarian state left rich merchants in
peace so long as they did not threaten it, in a word so long as they did not “grow
too big for their boots”. But it always kept a wary eye on them.
As Jacques Gernet writes in Daily life in China on the eve of Mongol
invasion 1250-76 (p. 61ff) regarding the Song China,
many merchants did became rich but they failed to create a “class”, like the
Third Estate in France or similar propertied classes elsewhere in Western Europe
that managed to first win political representation and later power. In China,
by contrast, there was a strong central government from the start to check the
power of merchants or anybody else. A similar theme is reprised by Debin Ma in his
paper on fiscal capacity of the Chinese state and the Great Divergence (“Rock, Scissors, Paper”): “…in China, the precocious rise of
absolutism [centralized state based on hierarchically-organized bureaucracy] with
the absence of any representative institution ensured that the economic rents
from the control of violence were firmly in the hands of political interest divorced
from those of commercial and property
interest” (pp. 26-7). It was surely not a government at the behest of the
bourgeoisie.
This leads us to the present-day
China. The current Communist-party dominated government, and the distribution
of political power between it and the already formed capitalist class, is reminiscent
of this traditional relationship. The government is helpful to the interests of
the bourgeoisie but only so long as these interests do not run contrary to the objectives
of the state (that is, of the elite that runs the state).
The distinction between state-owned,
purely privately-owned and a myriad of ownership arrangements in-between (state-owned
corporation raising private capital on the stock-exchange, communal property
mixed with private property, state firms with foreign private participation
etc.) is quite blurred in today’s China. Communist-party organizations exist
within fully privately-owned companies. For sure, they may be useful for capitalists
to the extent that they are able to coopt such organizations to lobby the
party-state on their behalf. But differently, their presence can also be enervating
as they are yet another constituency to be pleased and bribed or another body
that could, if such is the political climate, turn against capitalists. And do that
regardless of what formal ownership structure and the rights are.
Even
the Chinese official statistics have difficulties catching the distinctions so numerous
are the forms of ownership, and so many are different rights of ownership from ability
to dispose and sell the assets to usufruct only. This multitude of ownership
and corporate structures was one of the main headaches for the unconditional
partisans of the Washington Consensus who insisted on the importance of clearly
defined property rights for growth. It was impossible to fit China with its
myriad of property relationships into the neoliberal straightjacket. Moreover some
of the most murky types of ownerships, like Township and Village Enterprises,
registered the most spectacular rates of growth. (M. Weitzman and C. Wu had an excellent
paper on that).
But will Chinese capitalists who
exist and thrive in this jungle of ownership types and uncertain property
rights, forever acquiesce to that particular role where their formal rights can
be limited or revoked at any moment, and they are under the constant state tutorship;
or will they as they become stronger and
more numerous, organize, influence the state, and finally take it over as it
happened in Europe? The European path as
sketched by Marx seems in many respect to have certain iron logic: economic
power tends to emancipate itself and to look after, or impose, its own
interests. If capitalists have economic power in their hands, how can they be stopped?
But, on the other hand, almost two millennia of that uneasy and unequal partnership
between the Chinese state and Chinese business represents a formidable obstacle,
knit of tradition and inertia, that might keep the state autonomous and on what
Arrighi calls the Smithian path.
Thus the question of democratization
of China needs to be posed in a very different fashion from what we normally
do; the key question is whether Chinese capitalists will come to control the state and, in order
to do so, use representative democracy as its tool. In Europe and the United States,
that tool was used by capitalists very carefully; it was administered in homeopathic doses
as the franchise expanded often at the snail’s pace, and was retracted whenever
there was a potential threat to property-owning classes (as in England after
the French Revolution or in France after the Restauration, or in Hungary and somewhat
less in Austria throughout the existence of the Dual Monarchy). But by 1918, it
was politically impossible to continue with the imposition of literacy tests or
income censuses, and even the Southern United States were ultimately pressured
by the Civil Rights Act of 1965, to stop using a variety of means to
disenfranchise voters. Chinese democracy, if it comes, would thus be, in the legal
sense, of one-person one-vote, that is, of the kind observed elsewhere. Yet given
the weight of history, the precarious nature and still limited size of the propertied
classes (one study of the middle class in China puts it at 1/5th of
the urban population), it is not sure whether it could be maintained. It failed
in the first two decades of the 20th century, may it be re-established
with greater success one hundred years later?
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.