I enjoyed
tremendously Mary
Beard’s “Confronting the classics”. Beard is the most engaging writer, her
style is fresh and open, and she treats the ancient and the modern world as a
continuum which to today’s reader makes the ancient world closer and more easily understandable.
It is a book, I believe, directed both to dilettante amateurs of ancient history and
to the professionals in the field. The reason for the latter is that the book
is a collection of some thirty Beard’s reviews of books on the ancient world written
by her peers. Thus, I guess, the original reviews were very likely to have been
written for and read by the top professionals in the field.
Beard covers
what I would call the “high-school
antiquity”, that is the antiquity that most of us have studied in the high
school, which includes the Peloponnesian Wars, Alexander the Great, The Roman
republic and the Punic Wars, and the peak of the Roman Empire. She brings, at
least for me, a very fresh look at a number of people and issues (I will mention
some below), but I feel a bit of a regret
that she has not engaged, at least not in this book, with less well-known
and more difficult periods, especially with the crisis of the 3rd
and 4th centuries and the rise of Christianity.
I would like
to focus this review on three issues: methodology, role of the individual in history,
and a bit of economics (as you would expect).
An overwhelming
impression that one retains from Beard’s book is how fragmentary our knowledge
of the ancient world is, and how despite a seeming abundance of material
evidence (objects of art and daily life, writings, skeletons etc.) many questions
will probably never be answered. This fundamental lack of knowledge allows
Beard to question our received wisdom: was Hadrian really so much better than
Nero?, was Alexander a military genius or an arrogant, drunken youth endowed
with incredibly good luck (which might have run out had he not died young)?,
and the perennial question of whether Caeser’s assassination was a tyrannicide.
This lack of
knowledge leads ancient historians to employ the methodology that Beard
beautifully deconstructs in the most devastatingly negative review of any book
in this volume, Anthony Birley’s “Hadrian: The restless emperor”. The methodology
used by Burley and many others is “a combination of scholarship, conjecture and
fiction”. Scholarship is based on a rather narrow interpretation of the
evidence. But since that evidence, even for Hadrian, is scant (writings on his
reign date for at least a century after it ended), the authors have to resort
to conjuncture. The tell-tale terms are “seems”, “he must”, “it might be” “it was
done in such-and-such way, no doubt”, “they would have been”, “presumably”,
“the odds are” etc. Beard provides a number of such examples, and putting them
together amount to a devastating indictment of the approach. And soon, after conjecture,
fiction takes over. Why is this bad? Because, Beard writes, “the issue is that
this veneer of scrupulous scholarship (“I shall claim nothing as fact that I
cannot authenticate”) turns out to act a brilliant alibi for outright fiction”.
(p. 173).
This made me
think of the same approach used in economics. Since it has become impossible to
claim causality between two phenomena unless extremely stringent criteria are satisfied,
economists have taken to masking this fact by a legalistic use of language, very
similar to what ancient historians do when they “conjecture” (that is, make up)
things. The historians do not write that they have a proof that Hadrian walked along
the Hadrian wall; they write that “he no doubt was expected to make on-the-foot
review”. Of course, the objective is to tell the reader that indeed he did do such
a review, but to cover oneself academically through the use of the conditional.
Economists are given a Faustian choice of either not publishing anything since
they fail to have a proof of causality, or publishing articles that go out of
the way to claim that they discuss only “associations” while in reality they convey
to their readers the impression that it is really of causality they are
speaking. For if the writer really believed that he has uncovered only a mere
association, what would be the use of such a finding? Thus both sciences resort
to a massive cover-ups.
After I became
so thoroughly convinced by validity of Beard’s critique, I started paying
closer attention to the weasel words that she so aptly identified. And, lo and behold, most of them were there when
she too discusses events for which conjecture is the best we can come up with! I
did not go back to the earlier reviews to look for such words, but in only two
reviews following her demolition of Hadrian’s biographer, there are terms such
as “almost certainly”, “most likely”, “we can only wonder” etc. So, it seems
that even when we do know what should be done, we are, given the state of our knowledge,
unable to follow our own rules---for otherwise we shall publish nothing at all.
Thus conjecture
and perhaps fiction is best we can do in discussing Hadrian or Nero (or anybody
else in the ancient world). It is here that Beard introduces some really
interesting points. Alter showing the similarities between Nero and Hadrian (their
peripatetic careers, admiration--kowtowing as some Romans would no
doubt see it--- for Greek language and culture, unconventional behavior, love
of luxury) she asks whether their rules were really so much different as we conventionally
believe. Could not the ideas about the qualities of their rules have been
largely conveyed by the elite opinion
that prevailed after their deaths? Since Nero was assassinated, the assassins
had to claim that his rule was disastrous; Hadrian died in his bed, was
succeeded by Antonius Pius, hand-picked by Hadrian, was deified and remained
forever enshrined as a “good emperor”. But for the majority of the population (who
did not seem to mind, or might have rather enjoyed, Nero’s extravagances), was
there any difference?
The problem
with ancient history is that paucity of evidence does not allow us (except in some
obvious cases like the Gracchi or Caesar) to even so much as glimpse the social
forces that were opposing or supporting various emperors. We thus end up in the
unfortunate position of judging emperors solely by their, largely attributed,
personal character. We have “good” emperors, and we have “bad” emperors. This
is obviously a very simplistic view of studying history. However, this simplistic
view has in popular culture gone further than explaining only the ancient
history and today it informs most of our thinking about the contemporary world. Demonization of individuals without any
account being taken of the context within which they operate (all evils of Iraq
are due to Saddam—we know now how accurate that view was, or of Syria to Assad,
or of Russia to Putin, or of Iran to Ahmadi-Nejad (remember him?)) is made of the
exactly the same materiel as Robert Graves’
ubication of all the world’s deviousness in Livia (and Beard is scathing about
Graves and even more so of the BBC adaptation). For Rome perhaps we cannot do better since we
know so little about the social conditions under Hadrian or Nero, but for the
present world we surely can.
Finally, let
me come to economics which play a very small role in Beard’s reviews (and presumably
in the books she reviews). I found most interesting her discussion of slavery
in relation to Henrik
Mouritsen, and Keith
Bradley and Paul Cartledgge (eds.) books on the topic. There are two huge issues
there. First, Rome is among all known societies with extensive slavery the
only one where manumission was practiced on an extensive scale. Beard believes that ¾ of the population were freedmen (liberati) or descendants of freedmen. We
do not understand what led owners to such massive granting of liberty. Was it
because holding people as slaves was uneconomical (in the old age), or because
many developed personal relations with domestic slaves (sex and marriage)? But
the former cannot explain the scale of manumissions of younger slaves, the
latter cannot be something specific to Rome (nor can explain manumission of
non-domestic slaves). So, according to Beard, we have no answer. It is surely something
that economists should try to understand better, because in our explanation of
why Rome never developed labor-saving machinery, the cheap labor of slaves plays
a very important role. But the scale of manumissions bellies that interpretation.
Second, what
was the social structure of a society where ¾ of the population were freed slaves
or children of freed slaves? Here, I think a modern comparison with the role of
immigration in the United States may be useful. While being an immigrant does
carry a stigma in today’s US, that stigma is minimal (compared to Europe)
because almost every American born person has a parent or a grand-parent who
was an immigrant. Then stigmatizing others for something very close to what
oneself is, is indeed difficult and makes the societal acceptance of an
otherwise “negative condition” easier. In addition, as much as freedmen were proud
of having done well after being freed (as we can see from the inscriptions on
their funeral monuments), so the number of migrants who have done well further reduces
the generality of the stigma.
The fact that
I could write yet another review, perhaps of equal size, of Mary Beard book
show sufficiently how much both fun and useful it is. Now, I cannot wait to
read her “SPQR: A history of ancient Rome”.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.