The modern idea of citizenship, after the French Revolution, is
based on two pillars: one is voluntary
or compulsive participation in the political life of a community, the other is
the physical “grounding” in that political community. The participation means,
in democratic settings, that a citizen has a voice, the right to air opinions,
to vote for those who represent or lead him, and to be himself elected. In
non-democratic or not fully democratic settings, political participation is
often not only desirable but is required: citizens of the Soviet Union, Nazi
Germany, Francoist Spain were encouraged, or where necessary compelled, to take
part in mass public celebrations of the state whose citizens they were.
“Groundedness” means that citizens live in own countries (as their political
participation in the affairs of the country implies), earn most of their income
in own country, and spend most of it domestically.
The growth of the welfare state in the second half of the 20th
century, in the West and in the communist countries of Eastern Europe, has
added another facet to citizenship: the right to a number of benefits, from pensions to unemployment benefits that are available only to
contributors (i.e. citizens who work in their countries) or to citizens as such
without any contributory quid pro quo (as, for example, family allowances or
social assistance). The existence of the welfare state in a world of enormous income
differences between the countries has drawn a wedge between citizens of rich
countries that enjoy these benefits and citizens of poor countries that do not.
It has created a “citizenship rent” for those who are lucky to be citizens of
the rich countries; and “citizenship penalty” for others. Two otherwise identical citizens of France and Mali will
have entirely different sets of income-generating rights which stem from their citizenships
alone.
Moreover, the citizenship premium, as I show most
recently in “Capitalism Alone”, carries over to other incomes: our French
and Malian citizens can be equally educated, experienced, and hard-working, but
their wages will differ by a factor of 5 to 1, or even more, simply because one
of them works in a rich and another in a poor country. In fact, around
60% of our lifetime incomes is determined by country of citizenship.
In a globalized world composed of countries with vastly unequal
mean incomes citizenship has thus acquired an enormous, and well appreciated,
economic value. This is evident not only from the examples listed above but
from the freedom to travel without visa or any other permission (luxury of the
rich countries, as Zygmunt Bauman called it), support that one can expect from
his country offices abroad and the like.
But while the citizenship rent element has been reinforced in
the modern globalized capitalism, the other two pillars of citizenship (political participation
and groundedness) have been radically weakened. Citizenship has thus been effectively reduced
to financial rent alone.
Groundedness is sill common among many citizens. But its
importance fades as people move permanently or for long periods of time to other
countries: in some cases they migrate to richer countries to make more money
there (as migrants from Africa to Europe, or from Mexico to the United States
do), and in other cases, migrants from rich counties move to other, also rich countries,
as Americans do when they move to France (the latter category is often adorned
with the title of “expatriates”).
As they move to other countries they work there, make income
there, spend money there, and their financial sustenance gets “delinked” from
their country of citizenship. All sources of income can become degrounded: both
those of labor and capital. To see how ultimately the “degrounding” will work in a fully globalized
world, assume an elderly American expatriate who lives in France. A part of his
income may come from the work he does in France; another part, in the form of
US social security, may come from the US. But income behind that social security check may be earned from US
investments in China. Thus both physically and in terms of the origin of his
income, the American citizen will be “degrounded”. Or take a Philippine citizen
who works in the US. Similarly, his income would be earned in a foreign
country. If he is eligible for some citizenship-related income as a Philippine,
money earned to pay such benefits may in effect be earned by other Philippine citizens
working abroad, remitted back to their families in the Philippines, and then
taxed by the government.
Fully globalized country may be such that its capital income
comes from investments in foreign lands, its labor income from remittances sent
by its workers abroad, and most of its citizens be living abroad—and yet
receiving social and other benefits of citizenship.
Political participation in modern capitalism also wanes. With
a much more competitive society where one’s success is measured in terms of
economic power (wealth), people do not have enough free time or interest to be the idealized
citizens concerned with the political life of their city or nation. Hard work
for money takes most of their time. The rest of the waking time is taken by social
media, entertainment, family chores, or meetings with friends. Under normal
circumstances, time that they can devote to political issues is minimal. Electoral
turnouts in most developed democracies, by themselves a minimal requirement of
participation, cheap in effort and time, confirm that. They are low, especially
so among the youth. American presidential elections where people elect a person
with quasi regal powers have not once brought to the polling stations 60% of
the electorate in the past half-century. Elections for the EU parliament manage
to bestir about one-half of the eligible voters. This is not the product of
apathy only, but of busyness.
The decline in political participation and increasing degroudedness
imply that the two modern-era pillars of citizenship have largely been eroded. The
only remaining meaning of citizenship is the stream of income and advantages
that one receives if lucky to have been born or become citizen of a rich nation.
Citizenship has become an “ideal” category, a right devoid from the need to be
physically present in own country or to be interested in it: it physically incarnated in a script, a passport or in an
ID; it is a simple physical proof that one can aspire to its manifold advantages.
Countries that sell citizenship, from EU members to the small
Caribbean nations, do not make a mistake. Nor do their purchasers do. No one
expects the new citizens to either live much of their time in their new countries
(Chinese and Russians who buy Portuguese citizenship are required to spend there
one week per year), nor to participate in its social life. Not even to know the
language, much less history. Countries are exchanging an ideal category
(citizenship) that provides a set of rights over time against an amount of
money now, equal to the net present value of the bundle of these future
advantages.
The fact that citizenship has become a Polanyian “fictitious commodity”
has several implications that I discuss more fully in “Capitalism, Alone”. First,
we must move from the binary version of citizen-no citizens by introducing more
intermediary categories distinguished by the amounts of rights and duties they provide
(as indeed is already happening with permanent residents who are not fully-fledged
citizens). Second, migration can be seen as one of these intermediate positions
that do not automatically lead to full citizenship. Third, we should reconsider
the wisdom of giving electoral rights to people who do not live in a country
for whose leaders they vote, and who hence neither benefit nor suffer from the
choices they make. But all of these are topics for another piece.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.