I became somewhat peripherally involved in the debate on
long-term trends in global poverty that is raging these days in the WebSphere, prompted
first by some very
strong claims by Steven Pinker and Bill Gates, and then by an equally strong
rebuttal by Jason Hickel.
Max Roser, whose work is to be strongly commended, became
somewhat of a lateral casualty in this debate because it was his graph (based
essentially on the work of Martin Ravallion and the World Bank) that Pinker and
Gates quoted, and that Hickel disagreed with. Joe Hassel and Max
Roser have now written a detailed explanation of the data they used to
create the graph and how others (and themselves) have calculated global poverty
over the long-term. So, to be clear, I find Martin’s and Max’s work absolutely crucial
and indispensable for the understanding of long-term trends in this and a
number of other dimensions. But I disagree with the excessively political and
strident tone in which this work has been promoted by Steven Pinker (and more recently
by Bill Gates) and their disregard of many caveats which come with some of these
numbers.
As I mentioned in my tweet, there are (in my opinion) at
least four such caveats that Hickel rightly brings out explicitly. (He uses
other arguments too, but I do not comment on them.)
First, Maddison and Maddison-project data which are the only
game in town for both global poverty and global inequality and which I use in
my work too, do tend, like all GDP calculations,
to overestimate increase in real income where there is a transition from activities
that are not commodified to the same activities becoming commodified. GDP, as
is well-known, is geared to measure mostly monetized activity. At the time of
industrialization, as well as today during the ICT revolution, such
underestimation is likely to be significant. It is odd that people today would question
this—while we are going through a similar period of increased commodification
and a rising share of activities that are now marketable but hitherto were not.
Until Airbnb and Uber came along, your hosting friends of friends or driving
them to the airport was not part of GDP. Nowadays, it is because you will be
paid for such services. (The same is true for home activities that used to be performed
without monetary compensation mostly by women—and which, at some point, become
commercialized.)
Even more dramatic were, as Hickel points out, the changes
that occurred during the Industrial Revolution. Many activities performed
within households became monetized while people were often physically chased
away from, or disposed of, land, water and other rights that they had enjoyed for
free. I do not need to go into too many examples there—just take the enclosures,
or the land dispossession of Africans. This was not solely a transfer of
wealth, but seriously reduced income of those who had the right to the usus fructus of land, water or other
resources. Their reduced access to the actual goods and services was not recorded
in any income statistics. It is thus reasonable to think that both GDP growth rates
and the decline in poverty were overestimated.
Second, income distribution data for the 19th
century that we all use come almost entirely from the 2002 seminal paper
by Francois Bourguignon and Christian Morrisson (B-M). There are two more
recent papers, one by van
Zanden, Baten, Foldvari and van Leeuwen and one
by myself that used a somewhat different methodology (that is, more diversified
sources) in order to check the robustness of B-M findings. Both conclude that
B-M results stand, but in both papers (van Zanden et al. and Milanovic) the number
and/or reliability of these new sources are extremely limited. (I use social tables
to estimate countries’ distributions in the 19th century. But the
number of social tables that we have is very limited; both in terms of country
and temporal coverage.)
Furthermore, Morrisson’s original distributions, while made available
by the author, are unsourced. So, one cannot tell if they are right or wrong. But even if individual country distributions were right, many of them are
made to represent a vast variety of countries (say, Colombia, Peru and
Venezuela; or Cote d’Ivoire, Ghana, and Kenya; or “45 Asian countries”; or “37 African
countries”, all have the same distributions) because B-M divide the world into
33 “regions”, simply because information from most countries is lacking.
Fragility of such distributions has a particularly strong
effect on poverty numbers. It affects inequality somewhat less because, from
other (fragmentary) sources we know what are the ranges within which inequality
moves. But we know that less for poverty. The bottom line is that income distributions for the 19th
century are, to put it mildly, fragile.
Third, Hickel questions the use of $PPP 1.90 absolute poverty
line. There is a huge debate on this, and I will not enter into it—but it suffices
to look at the
critiques made by Thomas Pogge and Sanjay Reddy (regarding the underestimation
of the price level faced by the poor), large degree of arbitrariness with which
the poverty line of, at first $PPP1, and now $PPP 1.90, was drawn (see e.g.
Angus Deaton here),
or more recently the methodological questioning of the World Bank approach by
Bob Allen (here).
Hickel simply mentions these issues. They are real and they should not be
ignored.
Fourth, Hickel makes a more philosophical point that
economists (unlike say, anthropologists or historians) are less well-equipped
to deal with: human costs of the Industrial Revolution, from England to the
forced labor (and probably ten million dead) in the Congo and Java, to Bengal
famine (more than 10 million dead) to Soviet collectivization (more than 5 million
dead) and China’s Great Leap Forward (about 20 million dead). The dead enter
our calculations only to the extent that their deaths affect the estimated life
expectancy. (And in the B-M paper there is an attempt to calculate global
inequality over the past two centuries taking into account also changes in life
expectancy). But, otherwise, so far as poverty calculations are concerned, the
deaths have the perverse effect of reducing the population and increasing per
capita income since the marginal output of those who die as forced laborers or
from famine is zero or close to zero. Jason is right to bring up this point.
The effect of this last point is ambiguous though. While it
would—were we somehow able to account
for it—increase the costs of industrialization and make the gains, compared to
the pre-industrialization era, less, it would on the other hand improve the relative
position of the present with respect to
the era of industrialization—simply because such massive famines do not occur today,
or occur less frequently (e.g. North Korea, and before that in Ethiopia).
To conclude. In my opinion, Jason Hickel had brought up
several valid issues that most economists acknowledge as well (and have
actually frequently written about). However, others, once a graph is created, tend
to use the results less scrupulously or carefully in order to make political
points. This is why bringing these issues to the fore is valuable and should be
encouraged—and not shot down.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.